Interpreting the Quantum World II: What Does It Mean?

In the first installment of this series, we immersed ourselves in the quantum realm that lies beneath our everyday experience and discovered a universe that bears little resemblance to it. Instead of the solid, unambiguously well-behaved objects we’re familiar with, we encountered a unitary framework (\hat U) in which everything (including our own bodies!) is ultimately made of ethereal “waves of probability” wandering through immense configuration spaces along paths deterministically guided by well-formed differential equations and boundary conditions, and acquiring the properties we find in them as they rattle through a random pinball machine of collisions with “measurement” events (\hat M). This is all very elegant—even beautiful… but what does it mean? When my fiancé falls asleep in my arms, her tender touch, the warmth of her breath on my neck, and the fragrance of her hair hardly seem like mere probabilities being kicked around by dice-playing measurements. The refreshing drink of sparkling citrus water I just took doesn’t taste like one either. What is it that gives fire to this ethereal quantum realm? How does the Lord God breathe life into our probabilistic dust and bring about the classical universe of our daily lives (Gen. 2:7)? We finished by distilling our search for answers down to three fundamental dilemmas:

1)  What is this thing we call a wave function? Is it ontologically real, or just mathematical scaffolding we use to make sense of things we don’t yet understand?

2)  What really happens when a deterministic, well-behaved \hat U evolution of the universe runs headlong into a seemingly abrupt, non-deterministic \hat M event? How do we get them to share their toys and play nicely with each other?

3)  If counterfactual definiteness is an ill-formed concept, why are we always left with only one experienced outcome? Why don’t we experience entangled realities?

Physicists, philosophers, and theologians have been tearing their hair out over these questions for almost a century, and numerous interpretations have been suggested (more than you might imagine!). Most attempt to deal with 2), and from there, back out answers to 1) and 3). All deserve their own series of posts, so let me apologize in advance for only having time to do a fly-by of the more important ones here. In what follows I’ll give an overview of the most viable, and well-received interpretations to date, and finish with my own take on all of it. So, without further ado, here are our final contestants…

Copenhagen

This is the traditionally accepted answer given by the founding fathers of QM. According to Copenhagen, the cutting edge of reality is in \hat M. The world we exist in is contained entirely in our observations. Per the Born Rule, these are irreducibly probabilistic and non-local,and result in classically describable measurements. The wave function and its unitary history \hat U are mere mathematical artifices we use to describe the conditions under which such observations are made, and have no ontic reality of their own. In this sense, Copenhagen has been called a subjective, or epistemic interpretation because it makes our observations the measure of all things (pun intended :-) ). Although few physicists and philosophers would agree, some of the more radical takes on it have gone as far as to suggest that consciousness is the ultimate source of the reality we observe. Even so, few Copenhagen advocates believe the world doesn’t exist apart from us. The tree that falls in the woods does exist whether we’re there to see and hear it or not. What they would argue is that counterfactuals regarding the tree’s properties and those of whatever caused it to fall don’t instantiate if we don’t observe them. If no one sees the tree fall or experiences any downstream consequence of its having done so, then the question of whether it has or not is irreducibly ambiguous and we’re free to make assumptions about it.

Several objections to Copenhagen have been raised. The idea that ontic reality resides entirely in non-local, phenomenologically discrete “collapse” events that are immune to further unpacking is unsatisfying. Science is supposed to explain things, not explain them away. It’s also difficult to see how irreducibly random \hat M events could be prepared by a rational, deterministic \hat U evolution if the wave function has no ontic existence of its own. To many physicists, philosophers, and theologians, this is less a statement about the nature or reality than the universe’s way of telling us that we haven’t turned over enough stones yet, and may not even be on the right path.

For their part, Copenhagen advocates rightly point out that this is precisely what our experiments tell us—no more, no less. If the formalism correctly predicts experimental outcomes, they say, metaphysical questions like these are beside the point, if not flat-out ill-formed, and our physics and philosophy should be strictly instrumentalist—a stance for which physicist David Mermin coined the phrase “shut up and calculate".

Many Worlds

One response to Copenhagen is that if \hat U seems to be as rational and deterministic as the very real classical physics of our experience, perhaps that’s because it is. But that raises another set of questions. As we’ve seen, nothing about \hat U allows us to grant special status to any of the eigenstates associated with observable operators. If not, then we’re left with no reason other than statistical probability to consider any one outcome of an \hat M event to be any more privileged than another. Counterfactuals to what we don’t observe should have the same ontic status as those we do. If so, then why do our experiments seem to result in discrete irreducibly random and non-local “collapse” events with only one outcome?

According to the Many Worlds (MWI) interpretation, they don’t. The universe is comprised of one ontically real, and deterministic wave function described by \hat U that’s local (in the sense of being free of “spooky-action-at-a-distance”) and there’s no need for hidden variables to explain \hat M events. What we experience as wave function “collapse” is a result of various parts of this universal wave function separating from each other as they evolve. Entangled states within it will be entangled while their superposed components remain in phase with each other. If/when they interact with some larger environment within it, they eventually lose their coherence with respect to each other and evolve to a state where they can be described by the wave functions of the individual states. When this happens, the entanglement has (for lack of a better term) “bled out” to a larger portion of the wave function containing the previous entanglement, and the environment it interacted with, and states are said to have decohered. Thus, the wave function of the universe never actually collapses anywhere—it just continues to decohere into the separate histories of previously entangles states that continue with their own \hat U histories, never interacting with each other again. As parts of the same universal wave function, all are equally real, and questions of counterfactual definiteness are ill-formed.

The advantages of MWI speak for themselves. From a formal standpoint, a universe grounded on \hat U and decoherence that’s every bit as rational and well-behaved as the classical mechanics it replaced, certainly has advantages over one based on subjective hand grenade \hat M events. It deals nicely with the relativity-violating non-locality and irreducible indeterminacy that plague Copenhagen as well. And for reasons I won’t get into here, it also lends itself nicely to quantum field theory, and Feynmann path integral (“sum over histories”) methods that have proven to be very powerful.

But its disadvantages speak just as loudly. For starters, it’s not at all clear that decoherence can fully account for what we directly experience as wave function collapse. Nor is it clear how MWI can make sense of the extremely well-established Born Rule. Does decoherence always lead to separate well-defined histories for every eigenstate associated with every observable that in one way or another participates in the evolution of \hat U? If not, then what meaning can be assigned to probabilities when some states decohere and others don’t. Even if it does, what reasons do we have for expecting that it should obey probabilistic constraints?

And of course, we haven’t even gotten to the real elephant in the room yet—the fact that we’re also being asked to believe in the existence of an infinite number of entirely separate universes that we can neither observe, nor verify, even though the strict formalism of QM doesn’t require us to. Physics aside, for those of us who are theists this raises a veritable hornet’s nest of theological issues. As a Christian, what am I to make of the cross and God’s redemptive plan for us in a sandstorm of universes where literally everything happens somewhere to infinite copies of us all? It’s worth noting that some prominent Christian physicists like Don Page embrace MWI, and see in it God’s plan to ultimately gather all of us to Him via one history or another, so that eventually “every knee shall bow, and every tongue confess, and give praise to God (Rom. 14:11). While I understand where they’re coming from, and the belief that God will gather us all to Himself some day is certainly appealing, this strikes me as contrived and poised for Occam’s razor.

In the end, despite its advantages, and with all due respect to Hawking and its other proponents, I don’t accept MWI because, to put it bluntly, it’s more than merely unnecessary—it’s bat-shit crazy. According to MWI there is, quite literally, a world out there somewhere in which I, Scott Church (peace be upon me), am a cross-dressing, goat worshipping, tantric massage therapist, with 12” Frederick’s of Hollywood stiletto heels (none of that uppity Victoria’s Secret stuff for me!), and D-cup breast implants…

Folks, I am here to tell you… there isn’t enough vodka or LSD anywhere on this lush, verdant earth to make that believable! Whatever else may be said about this veil of tears we call Life, rest assured that indeterministic hand grenade \hat M events and “spooky action at a distance” are infinitely easier to take seriously. :D

De Broglie–Bohm

Bat-shit crazy aside, another approach would be to try separating \hat U and \hat M from each other completely. If they aren’t playing together at all, we don’t have to worry about whether they’ll share their toys. Without pressing that analogy too far, this is the basic idea behind the De Broglie-Bohm interpretation (DBB).

According to DBB, particles do have definite locations and momentums, and these are subject to hidden variables. \hat U is real and deterministic, and per the Schrödinger equation governs the evolution of a guiding, or pilot wave function that exists separate from particles themselves. This wave function is non-local and does not collapse. For lack of a better word, particles “surf” on it, and \hat M events acting on them are governed by the local hidden variables. In our non-local singlet example from Part I, the two electrons were sent off with spin-state box lunches. All of this results in a formalism like that of classical thermodynamics, but with predictions that look much like the Copenhagen interpretation. In DBB the Born Rule is an added hypothesis rather than a consequence of the inherent wave nature of particles. There is no particle/wave duality issue of course because particles and the wave function remain separate, and Bell’s inequalities are accounted for by the non-locality of the latter.

There’s a naturalness to DBB that resolves much of the “weirdness” that has plagued other interpretations of QM. But it hasn’t been well-received. The non-locality of its pilot wave \hat U still raises the whole “spooky action at a distance” issue that physicists and philosophers alike are fundamentally averse to. Separating \hat U from \hat M and duct-taping them together with hidden variables adds layers of complexity not present in other interpretations, and runs afoul of all the issues raised by the Kochen-Specker Theorem. We have to wonder whether our good friend Occam and his trusty razor shouldn’t be invited to this party. And like MWI, it’s brutally deterministic, and as such, subject to all the philosophical and theological nightmares that go along with that, not to mention our direct existential experience as freely choosing people. Even so, for a variety of reasons (including theories of a “sub-quantum realm” where hidden variables can also hide from Kochen-Specker) it’s enjoying a bit of a revival and does have its rightful place among the contenders.

Consistent Histories

As we’ve seen, the biggest challenge QM presents is getting \hat U and \hat M to play together nicely. Most interpretations try to achieve this by denying the ontological reality of one, and somehow rolling it up into the other. What if we denied the individual reality of both, and rolled them up into a larger ontic reality described by an expanded QM formalism? Loosely speaking, Consistent Histories (or Decoherent Histories) attempts to do this by generalizing Copenhagen to a quantum cosmology framework in which the universe evolves along the most internally consistent and probable histories available to it.

Like Copenhagen, CH asserts that the wave function is just a mathematical construct that has no ontic reality of its own. Where it parts company is in its assertion that \hat U represents the wave function of the entire universe, and it never collapses. What we refer to as “collapse” occurs when some parts of it decohere with respect to larger parts leading, it is said, to macroscopically irreversible outcomes that are subject to the ordinary additive rules of classical probability. In CH, the potential outcomes of any observation (and thus, the possible histories the universe might follow) are classified by how homogeneous and consistent they are. This, it’s said, is what makes some of them more probable than others. A homogeneous history is one that can be described by a unique temporal sequence of single-outcome propositions, such as, “I woke up” > “I got out of bed” > “I showered” … Those that cannot be, such as ones that include statements like “I walked to the grocery store or drove there” are not. These events can be represented by a projection operator \hat P from which histories can be built, and the more internally consistent they are (per criteria contained in a class operator \hat P), the more probable they are.

Thus, in CH \hat M is not a fundamental QM concept. The evolution of the universe is described by a mathematical construct, \hat U that can be interpreted as decohering into the most internally consistent (and therefore probable) homogeneous histories possible for it to. The paths these histories take give us a framework in which some sets of classical questions can be meaningfully asked, and other can’t. Returning to our electron singlet example, CH advocates would maintain that the wave function wasn’t entangled in any real physical sense. Rather, there are two internally consistent histories for the prepared electrons that could have emerged a spin measurement: Down/Up, and Up/Down. Down/Up/Up/Down isn’t a meaningful state, so it’s meaningless to say that the universe was “in” it. Rather, when the entire state of us/laboratory/observation is accounted for, we will find that the universe followed the history that was most consistent for that. There is no need to discriminate between observer and observed. Decoherence is enough to account for the whole history, so \hat M is a superfluous construct.

CH advocates claim that it offers a cleaner, and less paradoxical interpretation of QM and classical effects than its competitors, and a logical framework for discriminating boundaries between classical and quantum phenomena. But it too has its issues. It’s not at all clear that decoherence is as macroscopically irreversible as it’s claimed to be, or that by itself it can fully account for our experience of \hat M. It also requires additional projection and class operator constructs not required by other interpretations, and these cannot be formulated to any degree practical enough to yield a complete theory.

Objective Collapse Theories

Of course, we could just make our peace with \hat U and \hat M. Objective collapse, or quantum mechanical spontaneous localization (QMSL) models maintain that the universe reflects both because the wave function is ontologically real, and “measurements” (perhaps interactions is a better term here) really do collapse it. According to QMSL theories, the wave function is non-local, but collapses locally in a random manner (hence, the “spontaneous localization”), or when some physical threshold is crossed. Either way, observers play no special role in the collapse itself. There are several variations on this theme. The Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber theory for instance, emphasizes random collapse of the wave function to highly probably stable states. Roger Penrose has proposed another theory based on energy thresholds. Particles have mass-energy that, per general relativity, will make tiny "dents" in the fabric of space-time. According to Penrose, in the entangled states of their wave function these will superpose as well, and there will be an associated energy difference that entangled states can only sustain up to a critical threshold energy difference (which he theorizes to be on the order of one Planck mass). When they decohere to a point where this threshold is exceeded, the wave function collapses per the Born Rule in the usual manner (Penrose, 2016).

For our purposes, this interpretation pretty much speaks for itself and so do its advantages. Its disadvantages lie chiefly in how we understand and formally handle the collapse itself. For instance, it’s not clear this can be done mathematically without violating conservation of energy or bringing new, as-yet undiscovered physics to the game. In the QMSL theories that have been presented to date, if energy is conserved the collapse doesn’t happen completely, and we end up with left-over “tails” in the final wave function state that are difficult to make sense of with respect to the Born Rule. It has also proven difficult to render the collapse compliant with special relativity without creating divergences in probability densities (in other words, blowing up the wave function). Various QMSL theories have handled issues like this in differing ways, some more successfully than others, and research in his area continues. But to date, none of the theories on the table offers a slam-dunk.

The other problem QMSL theories face is a lack of experimental verification. Random collapse theories like Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber could be verified if the spontaneous collapse of a single particle could be detected. But these are thought to be extremely rare, and to date, none have been observed. However, several tests for QMSL theories have been proposed (e.g. Marshall et al., 2003; Pepper et al., 2012; or Weaver et al., 2016 to name a few), and with luck, we’ll know more about them in the next decade or so (Penrose, 2016).

Conclusion

There are many other interpretations of QM, some of which are more far-fetched than others. But the ones we’ve covered today are arguably the most viable, and as such, the most researched. As we’ve seen, all have their strengths and weaknesses. Personally, I lean toward Objective Collapse scenarios. It’s hard to believe that something as well-constrained and mathematically coherent as \hat U isn’t ontologically real. Especially when the alternative bedrock reality being offered is \hat M, which is haphazard and difficult to separate from our own subjective consciousness (the latter in particular smacks of solipsism, which has never been a very compelling, or widely-accepted point of view). Of the competing alternatives that would agree about \hat U, MWI is probably the strongest contender. But for reasons that by now should be disturbingly clear, it’s far easier for me to accept a non-local wave function collapse than its take on \hat M. Call me unscientific if you will, but ivory towers alone will never be enough to convince me that I have a cross-dressing, goat-worshipping, voluptuous doppelganger somewhere that no one can ever observe. Other interpretations don’t fare much better. Most complicate matters unnecessarily and/or deal with the collapse in ways that render \hat M deterministic.

It’s been said that if your only tool is a hammer, eventually everything is going to look like a nail. It seems to me that such interpretations are compelling to many because they’re tidy. Physicists and philosophers adore tidy! Simple, deterministic models with well-defined differential equations and boundary conditions give them a fulcrum point where they feel safe, and from which they think they can move the world. This is fine for what it’s worth of course. Few would dispute the successes our tidy, well-formed theories have given us. But if the history of science has taught us anything, it’s that nature isn’t as enamored with tidiness as we are. Virtually all our investigations of QM tell us that indeterminism cannot be fully exorcized from \hat M, and the term “collapse” fits it perfectly. Outside the laboratory, everything we know about the world tells us we are conscious beings made in the image of our Creator. We are self-aware, intentional, and capable of making free choices—none of which is consistent with tidy determinism. Anyone who disputes that is welcome to come up with a differential equation and a self-contained set of data and boundary conditions that required me to decide on a breakfast sandwich rather than oatmeal this morning… and then collect their Nobel and Templeton prizes and retire to the lecture circuit.

The bottom line is that we live in a universe that presents us with \hat U and \hat M. As far as I’m concerned, if the shoe fits I see no reason not to wear it. Yes, QMSL theories have their issues. But compared to other interpretations, its problems are formalistic ones of the sort I suspect will be dealt with when we’re closer to a viable theory of quantum gravity. When we as students are ready, our teacher will come. Until then, as Einstein once said, the world should be made as simple as possible, but no simpler.

When I was in graduate school my thesis advisor used to say that when people can’t agree on the answer to some question one of two things is always true: Either there isn’t enough evidence to answer the question definitively, or we’re asking the wrong question. Perhaps many of our QM headaches have proven as stubborn as they are because we’re doing exactly that… asking the wrong questions. One possible case in point… physicists have traditionally considered \hat U to be sacrosanct—the one thing that above all others, only the worst apostates would ever dare to question. Atheist physicist Sean Carroll has gone so far as to claim that it proves the universe is past-eternal, and God couldn’t have created it! [There are numerous problems with that of course, but they’re beyond the scope of this discussion.] However, Roger Penrose is now arguing that we need to do exactly that (fortunately, he’s respected enough in the physics community that he can get away with such challenges to orthodoxy without being dismissed as a crank or heretic). He suggests that if we started with the equivalence principle of general relativity instead, we could formulate a QMSL theory of \hat U and \hat M that would resolve many, if not most QM paradoxes, and this is the basis for his gravitationally-based QMSL theory discussed above. Like its competitors, Penrose’s proposal has challenges of its own, not the least of which are the difficulties that have been encountered in producing a rigorous formulation \hat M along these lines. But of everything I’ve seen so far, I find it to be particularly promising!

But then again, maybe the deepest secrets of the universe are beyond us. Isaac Newton once said,

“I do not know what I may appear to the world, but to myself I seem to have been only like a boy playing on the seashore, and diverting myself in now and then finding a smoother pebble or a prettier shell than ordinary, whilst the great ocean of truth lay all undiscovered before me.”

As scientists, we press on, collecting our shiny pebbles and shells on the shore of the great ocean with humility and reverence as he did. But it would be the height of hubris for us to presume that there’s no limit to how much of it we can wrap our minds around before we have any idea what’s beyond the horizon. As J. B. S. Haldane once said,

"My own suspicion is that the Universe is not only queerer than we suppose, but queerer than we can suppose." (Haldane, 1928)

Who knows? Perhaps he was right. God has chosen to reveal many of His thoughts to us. In His infinite grace, I imagine He’ll open our eyes to many more. But He certainly isn’t under any obligation to reveal them all, nor do we have any reason to presume that we could handle it if He did. But of course, only time will tell.

One final thing… Astute readers may have noticed one big elephant in the room that I’ve danced around, but not really addressed yet… relativity. Position, momentum, energy, and time have been a big part of our discussion today… and they’re all inertial frame dependent, and our formal treatment of \hat U and \hat M must account for that. There are versions of the Schrödinger equation that do this—most notably the Dirac and Klein Gordon equations. Both however are semi-classical equations—that is, they dress up the traditional Schrödinger equation in a relativistic evening gown and matching handbag, but without an invitation to the relativity ball. For a ticket to the ball, we need to take QM to the next level… quantum field theory.

But these are topics for another day, and I’ve rambled enough already… so once again, stay tuned! 

 

References

Haldane, J. B. S. (1928). Possible worlds: And other papers. Harper & Bros.; 1st edition (1928). Available online at www.amazon.com/s/ref=nb_sb_noss?url=search-alias%3Daps&field-keywords=Possible+worlds%3A+And+other+papers. Accessed May 17, 2017.

Marshall, W., Simon, C., Penrose, R., & Bouwmeester, D. (2003). Towards quantum superpositions of a mirror. Physical Review Letters, 91 (13). Available online at journals.aps.org/prl/abstract/10.1103/PhysRevLett.91.130401. Accessed June 9, 2017.

Pepper, B., Ghobadi, R., Jeffrey, E., Simon, C., & Bouwmeester, D. (2012). Optomechanical superpositions via nested interferometry. Physical review letters, 109 (2). Available online at journals.aps.org/prl/abstract/10.1103/PhysRevLett.109.023601. Accessed June 9, 2017.

Penrose, R. (2016). Fashion, faith, and fantasy in the new physics of the universe. Princeton University Press, Sept. 13, 2016. ISBN: 0691178534; ASIN: B01AMPQTRU. Available online at www.amazon.com/Fashion-Faith-Fantasy-Physics-Universe-ebook/dp/B01AMPQTRU/ref=sr_1_1?ie=UTF8&qid=1495054176&sr=8-1&keywords=penrose. Accessed May 16, 2017.

Weaver, M. J., Pepper, B., Luna, F., Buters, F. M., Eerkens, H. J., Welker, G., ... & Bouwmeester, D. (2016). Nested trampoline resonators for optomechanics. Applied Physics Letters, 108 (3). Available online at aip.scitation.org/doi/abs/10.1063/1.4939828. Accessed June 9, 2017.

About Scott Church

I am a landscape photographer and I.T. professional in the greater Seattle area. I graduated from the University of Washington with a Bachelor's in Mechanical Engineering and a Masters in Applied Physics, and in a former life, I was an aerospace engineer. When I'm not writing or at work I can be found plying the waters of the Pacific Northwest for salmon, trout, and steelhead, or bushwacking with my camera gear.
This entry was posted in Metaphysics, Physics. Bookmark the permalink.

29 Responses to Interpreting the Quantum World II: What Does It Mean?

  1. Aron Wall says:

    Just for the record, I think that probably all of these interpretations are false, although I have only fragmentary and foggy ideas about what should replace them. But I thought this rundown of common interpretations will be helpful, even if I don't agree that objective collapse is the way to go. And with that unendorsement, I'd like to thank you Scott, for an interesting and provocative post!

  2. kashyap vasavada says:

    Nice summary of interpretations. But I am surprised that you are leaning towards ontological reality of psi and U. To me it seems that the day you accepted wave-particle duality, you gave up on reality. None of us has seen a table (real!) which can be described as a particle or wave or both!

  3. Scott Church says:

    Thanks Aron and Kashyap! Actually, Aron, I do agree with you... ultimately, I think they're all probably false as well. At the very least, I don't believe any of them are complete. I support QMSL theories over other interpretations only to the extent that my gut tells me they get a little bit closer to the truth, and their shortcomings strike me as the sort that might be dealt with by a fully developed quantum gravity theory... if, and when we ever come up with one. Beyond that, however, I'm not at all ready to sign up as a card-carrying member of that camp. Right now, if I had to put money down, I'd side with Haldane... in the end, I think we'll find that the universe is queerer than we can suppose. We should never stop searching for answers of course... we wouldn't be scientists if we did, nor would our worship be complete. But I learned a long time ago that there will always be some mystery in Creation, and a point where we'll just have to take off our sandals and recognize that we're standing on holy ground (Exodus 3:5). :-)

  4. Mactoul says:

    I question the very notion of "a deterministic, well-behaved Û evolution of the universe". Wasn't QM formulated not for "the evolution of the universe"--a grandiose and scientifically dubious undertaking--but to interpret experiments on microscopic phenomena. The many problems and paradoxes mentioned are just created by unjustified extrapolation of the QM wavefunction of a specified microscopic system to the "entire universe"--whatever that means.

    Universe is defined as the totality of consistently interacting things. How do you ever know empirically that you have got the totality? The concept "universe" is thus non-empirical and thus can not be used in physics.
    Presumably the cosmologists are responsible for this notion of "wavefunction of the universe". Let them be!
    But an introduction to QM and its interpretations should avoid the dubious notions and stick with what is experimentally tried and true--which none of the cosmologists' notions are!

  5. Valentin says:

    It would be very interesting to me which implications would have any of these interpretations of Quantum World for Hawking-Hartle's model and for Vilekin's model of the apparition of the universe.

  6. TY says:

    Scott and Aron,
    You did touch on the notion of the “observer” in measurement and I would like to know Aron's thoughts and yours on whether there is a problem in QM from the very outset and that is assumes the "observer" is outside the mathematical formulations or descriptions of the physical world. But from what I’ve learned from the literature, even a physical device (like a Geiger counter) that is supposed to be taking the “measurements” becomes part of the system. So what is being measured?

    All that aside and the many paradoxes, QM works! so I won't say just because of the unexplained or explainable puzzles that QM is invalid. As your review suggests, there is no better theory or hypothesis.

    Good discussion.

  7. Scott Church says:

    @Valentin, the Hartle-Hawking model is one solution of the Wheeler-DeWitt equation, which essentially, is a semiclassical boundary constraint on the wave function of the universe. Inasmuch as various interpretations of QM differ as to whether such a universal wave function exists, it would only be consistent with those that allow for one. Of the interpretations I discussed here, that would include de Broglie–Bohm, MWI, and Consistent Histories, but not Copenhagen or QMSL theories. Wikipedia has a good tabular comparison of these, and many other interpretations regarding a universal wave function, as well as the other points I covered.

    @Ty, I guess it depends on what we mean by "problem". As we saw, these, and other interpretations differ on the role of "observers" and "measurements" in QM, and to the extent that we're left with a lot of underlying mysteries about what both mean, yes. But that said, when Aron and I say that all of these interpretations are probably wrong, we are not talking about QM itself. As I commented in my first post, QM is arguably the most successful scientific theory in history. The one thing no one of consequence disputes is that as-is, it tells us a great deal about the universe. What's problematic is how we interpret that message ontologically and epistemologically, and whether any deeper, currently "hidden" layers of physics are involved. In any event, it's safe to say that whatever the real meaning of it all is, and however the latter question is answered, QM is showing us some of God's thoughts. If/when it is supplanted by a viable quantum gravity or so-called "everything" theory, you can rest assured that theory will reduce to QM in low-energy limits, the way general relativity reduces to classical mechanics. In their respective realms, none of these is any less valid than they've always been. :-)

  8. Tom Rudelius says:

    Nice post, Scott. Two comments and a question: I think it's worth emphasizing that there is no such thing as "\emph{the} wavefunction" or "*the* observer" in the Copenhagen interpretation--the wavefunction is defined relative to an observer, and the question of what you want to count as observer vs. system is subjective. Of course, this leaves open the problem of defining ontic reality, but at least it solves other issues e.g. the Wigner's friend paradox.

    I disagree somewhat with the claim "Science is supposed to explain things, not explain them away." A common tactic in high-energy physics is to show that if a problem can't be solved, it can at least be put into a strong coupling regime where we don't expect to find a solution (see e.g. the last sentence of Witten's seminal '95 paper.) In the present case, it's unclear to me that science should be able to do more than to explain outcomes of experiments.

    Finally, a question: how would the MWI proponent explain black hole complementarity? The complementarity solution to the information paradox relies on the idea that no observer can simultaneously observe both copies of the information. But if MWI gives "observers" no special status, how would its proponents justify this solution? Or would they argue that complementarity is not the right answer to the information paradox?

  9. Scott Church says:

    Thanks @Tom! I would agree with both of your comments. When discussing Copenhagen, my reference to "the" wave function and observer was just a choice of words when I was addressing them and wasn't meant to imply that per that interpretation they could be objectively rather than subjectively defined. In fact, the very subjectivity of Copenhagen is a big part of why many find it unsatisfying. And yes, in physics we often cannot do better than explaining the outcomes of experiments, and in the absence of anything more, that's where we stand. As Mermin said, "shut up and calculate". But the real holy grail, I think, is a model that's paradigmatically, as well as mathematically complete--one that does give us a more ontic explanation of reality as opposed to a merely epistemic one that we can calculate from. If the latter is what God has chosen to reveal to us so far then we accept that with grateful hearts. Pork chops can be wonderful, especially when grilled with the right marinade or rub, and to date, Copenhagen has been a fine pork chop. But God willing... that bacon-wrapped filet mignon is what we came out for! :-)

    Regarding MWI and black hole complementarity, to be honest, I'm not familiar enough with that issue to comment. Aron, do you have any thoughts...?

  10. Mactoul says:

    Isn't it curious that none of the traditional treatments and examples of QM deal with the "wavefunction of the universe". The exposition here could deal with simple quantum mechanical examples such as double-silt experiment and how does it fares under various interpretations.

  11. Aleksy says:

    Dear Scott,

    I was wondering what are your thoughts on IP's video 'Quantum Mechanics Debunks Materialism'

    https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=4C5pq7W5yRM

    All the best,

    Aleksy

  12. Scott Church says:

    @Aleksy, having watched the presentation, it seems a bit much to me to claim that QM debunks Materialism--at least in the usual sense of that term, which is synonymous with atheism. What it does refute is the deterministic classical worldview that remains completely characterized apart from observers, but strictly speaking, that doesn't require one to believe in God. But that said, I do believe that like the big bang (or more properly, Concordance cosmology), it raises some pretty significant issues for Materialism that aren't easily dismissed by its advocates. Not the least of these is the belief that bedrock reality--that which simply is--is restricted to physical matter alone, apart from any sort of consciousness or mind. At the very least, I'd say that QM renders it extremely difficult (if not impossible) for atheists to insist that science leaves no room for God without resorting to the same kind of dogmatic assertion they rightly accuse many fundamentalists of. [As a matter of fact, my next post (which I hope to have ready next week) will be addressing some of these very issues.]

    Cheers! :-)

  13. Christopher says:

    Hello Scott and Aron,
    I am curious what your thoughts are on quantum Bayesianism? - https://www.quantamagazine.org/quantum-bayesianism-explained-by-its-founder-20150604/ Thank you for the interesting post!

  14. Scott Church says:

    @Christopher, my apologies... Once again, I'm not familiar enough with QB to comment on it, so I'll defer to Aron on this as well. Thanks! :-)

  15. valentin says:

    Many thanks, Scott!

    Aron wrote that many quantum cosmologists prefer a 'many world' interpretation for their model of the origin of the universe. Why do they not equally prefer for example a 'de Broglie-Bohm' interpretation? Is this interpretation more controversial than the 'many worlds' one? Is the its 'hidden variables' idea as wild as the 'multiplication of entities' idea suggested by the 'many worlds' interpretation?

  16. Scott Church says:

    @Valentin, those hidden variables are DBB's biggest problem. In fact, it was one of the first attempts to leverage them to rescue physics from Copenhagen, and some would call it the hidden variables theory. Personally, I'm with you in that I don't consider hidden variables to be as wild as an infinite multiplication of entities. However, they do run afoul of the Bell inequalities and Kochen-Specker theorem. While DBB is enjoying a bit of a comeback as I mentioned, inasmuch as it's dependent on them, these are considerable hurdles to clear and few physicists are convinced that it will be able to.

    As for MWI, quantum cosmology attempts to apply QM to the origin and evolution of the universe as a whole, and as such will only admit interpretations that allow for a universal wave function. So if MWI is favored by quantum cosmologists it's probably because from a formal standpoint it's the most workable of those that do.

    Best. :-)

  17. valentin says:

    Many thanks, Scott!

  18. Andrew says:

    Good job, Scott. This is well written and quite interesting!

  19. Aron Wall says:

    To try to answer some questions about these interpretations...

    As I tried to make clear in my QM I post, QM can be thought of as a modification of the usual rules of probability theory. It is one of the few ways to consistently modify probability theory that seems to make any kind of sense at all. Now, when it comes to classical probability theory, Bayesians believe that probability is best thought of as an individual's personal or "subjective" credences about how the world is (which are, however, rationally constrained by the axioms of probability theory, and I would say also by various rules of thumb about how to estimate prior probabilities). So a "Quantum Bayesian" would, it seems, interpret the wavefunction in much the same way: as an individual's best set of credences. As somebody sympathetic to classical Bayesianism, I have a prediliction to be sympathetic to this too...

    However, the Kochen-Specker theorem implies that, if we want to think of all quantum operators as having well defined values in some ontological sense, this does not just violate classical probability theory. It also violates classical logic, i.e. it is simply not possible to simultaneously assign a true physical value to all operators. That seems worse that just modifying probability theory...

    The contemporary "QBist" view avoids this problem by taking things in a radically subjective direction, by denying that we can talk about any kind of objective state of the universe; just the experiences of ourselves as a single observer. In this view, if I understand them correctly, QM is a set some pragmatically justified rules to predict what we observe. But it seems unsatisfying not to have a story about what is "really" going on with the system. So to my tastes, this is too subjective.

    Bohmian interpretations avoid conflict with Kochen-Specker in a different way; by saying that one privileged set of commuting operators (e.g. positions) have objectively well defined values, while others (e.g. momenta) do not. Position is the choice usually used in nonrelativistic QM, but this is arbitrary. However, it seems hard to decide how to generalize this to QFT. Many important symmetries (such as Lorentz invariance) seem to be broken, which is one reason many physicists find it unaesthetic. So I'm not sure how to make a Bohmian interpretation of quantum cosmology, but it probably involves some arbitrary choices.

  20. Aron Wall says:

    Tom,
    A somewhat more "objective" way of defining Black Hole Complementarity, is to say that it's okay for observables at spacelike separation to fail to commute, so long as they are not in a single causal patch of the universe. And I think many of its proponents also believed in MWI.

    However, Black Hole Complementarity is currently in very serious trouble as a result of the "firewalls" thought experiment. Joe Polchinksi, at any rate, views this at refuting his previous belief in Complementarity.

  21. Ned says:

    Hello all,
    What do you think of this response to the problem of hidden variables for Bohemian mechanics (I copied the text from this video, which looks to be put forward by academics/non-quacks):
    " The name Hidden Variable Theories refers to theories that substitute or supplement the wave function of QM by some other variable. This definition also applies to BM, where the wave function is supplemented by the actual position of the particle. Now, you can decide by yourself whether the term hidden is appropriate or not for particle positions. No-go theorems are not general theorems about hidden variables as defined above, even if they are often invoked when speaking in general terms about hidden variables. To really understand if they say something about BM or not, general terms are not sufficient, and we have to look at the theorems closer. For example, Kochen-Specker theorem says that it is not possible to describe quantum mechanical observables by variables independent of the experimental set-up. But in BM the outcomes of experiments are described precisely by quantum mechanical observables, not by classical variables, in perfect agreement with the theorem. Only positions are described by usual variables in addition to the wave function, but the Bohmian positions are the actual positions occupied by the particles during the whole evolution, and not results of position measurements, that are also described by quantum observables.In contrast, Bell’s Theorem can be formulated without even speaking about hidden variable theories: the theorem states that some predictions of QM, well confirmed by several experiments, can not be explained by any local theory. And BM is nonlocal, as well as QM is. In fact BM inspired Bell to investigate non-locality, finally leading him to discover his famous inequalities. Bell was one of the most prominent proponents of BM and wrote many articles explaining it in great detail. Bell’s Theorem is often misunderstood and reduced to a mere statement that excludes the possibility of substituting QM with a local classical theory. Conversely, it is an extremely important result, that requires us to change drastically our conception of the world, and that is the source of many difficulties in the reconciliation between QM and Relativity. " The video I took this from is here - https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=JV-l3gk6i9Y&index=12&list=PL7LbfRoKBR5OpRjt8toBOmzqGjH7zaM1m

  22. Andrew says:

    Scott can I ask you a simple question about the MWI? ... Do you thin protective measurements (if we had one) would be a problem for MWI? The way I think of it is, if you have a super imposed wave function in one universe then it doesn't correspond to a multiverse.

  23. Scott Church says:

    Hello @Andrew,

    To be honest, I'm not sure what you mean by "protective measurements". [Aron, do you have any thoughts on that...?]

    The larger problem here is that these days terms like "worlds" or "universes" are used in a number of confusing ways, and the most common ones are largely misnomers. MWI is one case in point. What it refers to as "worlds", or "parallel universes" are, as you said, just separately decohering histories within a single universal wave function. Something similar happens with the so-called inflationary "multiverse". In that case, there's a single eternally inflating spacetime within which non-inflating reheated regions appear as "bubbles", or "bubble universes" when the inflaton relaxes to a ground state there.

    In both cases, whether one refers to the larger wave function or spacetime as the universe, or their separate decohered/reheated regions as "universes" is a choice of words. Unfortunately, for largely sensationalistic reasons that sell more books and magazines, this is rarely clarified in the popular press. :-)

  24. Andrew says:

    Sure, well I agree and also decoherence is exponential so I suppose it doesn't really make sense to talk about total separate parallel worlds.

  25. Nesar Ali Titumir says:

    There are recent papers by Ward Struyve and Daniel Sudarsky on possible applications of the GRW and Pilot wave theory in cosmology. Any comments about those papers?

  26. flavio says:

    Scott,(and Aron)
    I know this is a post about QM, but i want to discuss it's implications on relativity. Can relativity survive a non-local interpretation of QM?I mean, is there is a "spooky action at a distance",there could be relations of absolute Simultaneity. Quentin smith thinks we should go back to how relativity was back in lorentz view, something he (and WL Craig also supports.) and adopt a bohmian view of QM.

  27. flavio says:

    Besides, i've been told that Quantum field theory is local. IS it because it needs to be local because it is a theory that incorporates special relativity? And if QFT is local,doesn't that imply that QM is, a fortiori, local?

  28. Scott says:

    Hello Flavio. There are local and non-local interpretations of QM, the more prominent of which are discussed in this post. Aron can probably speak to the under-the-hood details better than I, but the Bohmian view you referred to is based on a non-local pilot wave and thus doesn't avoid the "spooky action at a distance" problem. And I believe the primary reason Quentin-Smith and WL Craig are drawn to it is that it's friendlier to presentism (that is, an A-Theory view of time). While that view of time and relativity can be made to work, and does offer solutions to some thorny philosophical problems, it is considerably messier and in my opinion and Aron's, creates far more problems than it solves. Aron addresses some of these issues in more depth in his God and Time series, most notably Part III.

  29. flavio says:

    Thanks for the reply, Scott. But the point i was trying to make is that, IF there is a "spooky action ata distance", THEN there are relations of absolute(causal) simultaneity, which is incompatible with relativity.Thats why i opt for local interpretations of QM. And what about quantum field theory, is it "local" in this sense?

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

*

You may use these HTML tags and attributes: <a href="" title=""> <abbr title=""> <acronym title=""> <b> <blockquote cite=""> <cite> <code> <del datetime=""> <em> <i> <q cite=""> <strike> <strong>

help-hint.png
My comment policy, including help with leaving LaTeX equations. Place these between double dollar signs, for example: $$\hbar = 1.05 \times 10^{-34} \text{J s}$$. Avoid using > or < since these may be misinterpreted as html tags.
If your comment fails to appear do NOT submit it again.  Instead, email me so I can rescue it from the spam filter.  You can find my email by clicking on "webpage".